theoretics wrote:Is there a difference between 'mistaking the sufficient condition for the necessary condition' and 'mistaking the necessary condition for the sufficient condition'? I can sort of see a difference, but I feel like it could be phrased either way and still be the same flaw.
The explanations from pkraft1 quoted below are correct and my explanations build on his examples.
Depending on which materials/source you're using for prep (which company's class or books), there are easy to remember shorthand labels/descriptions for these two different common flawed uses of conditional premises.
premise A --> B (If A then B, All A's are B's, etc.)
This flawed reasoning method/pattern/utilization: B is true, therefore A must be true
is mistaking the necessary condition for the sufficient condition.
In the LSAT prep world this flawed method of reasoning is commonly called invalid/incorrect/mistaken reversal since the reasoning method using the conditional premise to arrive at the conclusion reverses the conditional premise in a logically invalid way by treating it as if the premise established B --> A rather than A --> B. Hence, the flawed reasoning improperly reversed the conditions from their valid sufficient vs. necessary positions/mistakenly assumed that the sufficient/necessary relationship between the conditions is the reverse of what the premise established.
same premise A --> B
Flawed reasoning method/pattern/utilization: A is false, therefore B must be false
is mistaking the sufficient condition for the necessary condition.
In the LSAT prep world this flawed method of reasoning is commonly called invalid/incorrect/mistaken negation since the reasoning method using the conditional premise to arrive at the conclusion negates both sides of the conditional premise relationship in a logically invalid way by treating it as if the premise logically established ~A --> ~B. That flawed negation of both conditions while leaving them in the same diagrammatic sufficient and necessary condition places in the arrow diagram is the contrapositive of conditional premise B --> A, the flawed reversal of the given A--> B conditional relationship premise.
Under the premise, condition 'A' being true is sufficient to guarantee that B must also be true, but the premise by itself DOES NOT exclude the possibility that there could be other sufficient conditions that could also guarantee that B must be true other than condition 'A' being true. Thus, this flawed method of treating the sufficient condition 'A', (which guarantees that condition 'B' must be true), as if it also establishes that the sufficient condition 'A' being false guarantees that necessary condition 'B' must also be false invalidly assumes/mistakes/treats the sufficient condition 'A' as if it's a necessary condition for B to be able to be true because the premise ( A --> B ) only establishes that 'A' is a sufficient condition, not a necessary condition for condition 'B' to be true.
Sufficient conditions are called 'sufficient' because when you know the condition is true, it's enough to logically GUARANTEE that the necessary condition must also be true, whereas knowing that a necessary condition of a conditional relationship is true isn't enough to guarantee anything about the absolute logical truth (must be true or must be false) of the other condition in the relationship. Knowing that a necessary condition is true only establishes that the sufficient condition is possible/could be true, but logically doesn't guarantee anything absolute/must be true/must be false about the sufficient condition in the relationship.
Hope this isn't overly confusing. The foundations and concepts behind logically valid vs. invalid conditional reasoning methods usually take a little bit of time, practice and review to get familiar and comfortable with for most people during the important learning LSAT concepts/building your LSAT knowledge foundation phase of prepping for the test.
With standard conditional premises (not formal logic premises that use quantifiers Most or Some), an easy way to think about and remember their logically valid uses/valid methods of using them to establish logically correct conclusions vs. flawed ways they're frequently used to produce invalid/illogical/flawed conclusions is that you can only make a valid must be true inference/conclusion from a conditional premise when you know either one of two things: that the sufficient condition is true or that the necessary condition is false.
(You may already know this stuff, so feel free to disregard if so, I'm just trying to be thorough since I have no idea where in your prep journey you are.)
Since every standard conditional premise also implicitly establishes that the contrapositive of it is also a valid premise, a really easy way to remember when you can draw a valid MUST BE TRUE conclusion from conditional premises is that you can only make an absolute must be true/must be false conclusion about an element from a conditional premise when you know that the sufficient condition is true, meaning that the condition on the side the arrow points away from (the left side if you always draw your arrow diagrams with the arrow pointing to the right).
Premise: A --> B
contrapositive: ~B --> ~A
The contrapositive that's implicitly true/valid from every standard conditional premise is simply formed by both REVERSING AND NEGATING both conditions, so the valid implicit contrapositive of the original premise is ~B --> ~A.
With the original premise and its contrapositive properly diagrammed,
A --> B
~B --> ~A
you only need to and should only look at the left side of the diagrams to determine the valid must be true conclusions that can be drawn from the premise. If you know/are told that/it's established that a condition on the left side of the arrow diagram is true, then it must be true that the condition on the right side must be true. Knowing that a necessary condition (the ones on the right side of the arrow diagrams) is true doesn't allow you to conclude anything absolute (must be true or must be false) about the sufficient condition(s) on the other side/left side of the arrow diagram of the conditional premise.
If you diagram conditional premises and the contrapositive of each, you only need to focus your attention on the left side/sufficient condition side of the diagrams to quickly know what valid conclusions are supported/established by those premises when combined with other facts about which conditions are true or false (other premise(s) or info in answer choices that tell you certain condition(s) are true or false).
With the example A --> B conditional premise, knowing that the necessary condition of either the original premise or it's contrapositive is true (the conditions on the right side of the arrow diagrams) doesn't guarantee anything absolute about the truth of the sufficient conditions on the left side of the diagrams. So, knowing that necessary condition 'B' is true or that condition 'A' is false (necessary condition '~A' in the contrapositive), doesn't guarantee/establish whether the other/sufficient condition is true or false. If 'B' is true, it only supports the conclusion that condition 'A' COULD BE TRUE, but also leaves open the possibility that 'A' could be false. If 'A' is false (~A), 'B' could be true or could be false since knowing that a necessary condition is true does not guarantee anything absolute about the logical truth (for sure true or for sure false) of the sufficient condition in the conditional relationship.
----
In a nutshell:
mistaking a necessary condition for a sufficient condition = LSAT prep world labels invalid/incorrect/mistaken reversal of the explicitly given conditional premise.
mistaking a sufficient condition for a necessary condition = LSAT prep world labels invalid/incorrect/mistaken negation of the explicitly given conditional premise.
I hope this helps clear things up. Feel free to ask for clarification or anything since conditional reasoning is used in some complex/tricky ways in many LR questions of various question types including must be true, most strongly supported, strengthen, weaken, describe the flaw, sufficient assumption, necessary assumption, parallel reasoning and principle question types.
pkraft1 wrote:the difference is what the argument is utilizing. For example,
if a then b.
b
therefore a.
mistakes a necessary condition for a sufficient condition because it utilized what is actually a necessary condition as a sufficient condition.
On the other hand,
if a then b
not a
therefore not b.
mistakes a sufficient for a necessary.