"Always Almost Impossible" = "Always Impossible"?
Posted: Sat Mar 20, 2010 6:07 pm
This is stemming from my experience w/LRB, Pg. 162. I'm curious if this is how the LSAT views the word "almost" based on what the right answer was.
Law School Discussion Forums
https://www.top-law-schools.com/forums/
https://www.top-law-schools.com/forums/viewtopic.php?f=6&t=111624
I can't speak to that particular question, but I don't see how they could view those two things as equal. "Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible, and that is quite different than being always impossible.chicagobullsfan wrote:This is stemming from my experience w/LRB, Pg. 162. I'm curious if this is how the LSAT views the word "almost" based on what the right answer was.
I disagree with Powerscore's explanation, then. That statement doesn't "deny" that's possible, just states that people with a large number of demerits are overwhelmingly unlikely to be made into more responsible drivers.chicagobullsfan wrote:So their explanation in the next page says "the final sentence denies that drivers with a large number of demerit points who have also been convicted of a serious driving related offense can be made into more responsible drivers."
The last sentence states "Unfortunately it is always almost impossible to make drivers with a large number of demerit points more responsible drivers."
They are claiming always almost impossible = a full on denial?
How so? I genuinely curious. My reasonining is that if something is always X, then it is always X. In this case, X= "almost impossible." Thus, it's never impossible--just highly unlikely.Oblomov wrote: Actually, I think that it means that it is sometimes, but rarely, possible.
I think this part of your claim is faulty:AngryAvocado wrote:I can't speak to that particular question, but I don't see how they could view those two things as equal. "Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible, and that is quite different than being always impossible.chicagobullsfan wrote:This is stemming from my experience w/LRB, Pg. 162. I'm curious if this is how the LSAT views the word "almost" based on what the right answer was.
.. mostly because I can make the claim that it is almost always impossible for 1 + 1 to equal three and that would not entail that it is also always possible for 1 + 1 to equal three."Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible
Disregarding the modal logic stuff, in the context of the LSAT, I believe it's safe to reinterpret this statement as follows:chicagobullsfan wrote:So their explanation in the next page says "the final sentence denies that drivers with a large number of demerit points who have also been convicted of a serious driving related offense can be made into more responsible drivers."
The last sentence states "Unfortunately it is always almost impossible to make drivers with a large number of demerit points more responsible drivers."
They are claiming always almost impossible = a full on denial?
skip james wrote:I think this part of your claim is faulty:AngryAvocado wrote:I can't speak to that particular question, but I don't see how they could view those two things as equal. "Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible, and that is quite different than being always impossible.chicagobullsfan wrote:This is stemming from my experience w/LRB, Pg. 162. I'm curious if this is how the LSAT views the word "almost" based on what the right answer was.
.. mostly because I can make the claim that it is almost always impossible for 1 + 1 to equal three and that would not entail that it is also always possible for 1 + 1 to equal three."Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible
But it's sort of a tricky statement that you're making since you're talking about the possibility of a possibility rather than the possibility itself.
When I say it's almost always impossible for 1 + 1 to equal 3, then my statement entails that it is possible that it is possible that 1 + 1 equals 3 but that does not mean that it is, in fact possible that 1 + 1 equals 3.
I think you might have made a modal fallacy, but I'm not sure since I'm pretty rusty on that sort of stuff.
And actually, I just peeked at the LRB, and if you read it carefully, they actually do include the 'most' element into the necessary condition. They define R (or the second sentence of the problem as 'likely to be made responsible drivers'. Powerscore's logic here works, since the 'most' element is already embedded into the conditional.skip james wrote:Disregarding the modal logic stuff, in the context of the LSAT, I believe it's safe to reinterpret this statement as follows:chicagobullsfan wrote:So their explanation in the next page says "the final sentence denies that drivers with a large number of demerit points who have also been convicted of a serious driving related offense can be made into more responsible drivers."
The last sentence states "Unfortunately it is always almost impossible to make drivers with a large number of demerit points more responsible drivers."
They are claiming always almost impossible = a full on denial?
Most of the time, drivers with a large number of demerit point will not become more responsible drivers.
TITCRAngryAvocado wrote:skip james wrote:I think this part of your claim is faulty:AngryAvocado wrote:I can't speak to that particular question, but I don't see how they could view those two things as equal. "Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible, and that is quite different than being always impossible.chicagobullsfan wrote:This is stemming from my experience w/LRB, Pg. 162. I'm curious if this is how the LSAT views the word "almost" based on what the right answer was.
.. mostly because I can make the claim that it is almost always impossible for 1 + 1 to equal three and that would not entail that it is also always possible for 1 + 1 to equal three."Always almost impossible" means that's it's also always possible
But it's sort of a tricky statement that you're making since you're talking about the possibility of a possibility rather than the possibility itself.
When I say it's almost always impossible for 1 + 1 to equal 3, then my statement entails that it is possible that it is possible that 1 + 1 equals 3 but that does not mean that it is, in fact possible that 1 + 1 equals 3.
I think you might have made a modal fallacy, but I'm not sure since I'm pretty rusty on that sort of stuff.
First of all, "almost always impossible" =/= "always almost impossible."
Second, if something is almost impossible, it isn't quite impossible. If something isn't impossible, then it's possible by definition. I don't see how it's a modal fallacy if it must be one or the other and one of the options is ruled out.
I agree with 1 but not with 2.AngryAvocado wrote:
First of all, "almost always impossible" =/= "always almost impossible."
Second, if something is almost impossible, it isn't quite impossible. If something isn't impossible, then it's possible by definition. I don't see how it's a modal fallacy if it must be one or the other and one of the options is ruled out.
my oh my, this is profound.bgdddymtty wrote: Words have meanings.